Cubical¶
The Cubical mode extends Agda with a variety of features from Cubical Type Theory. In particular, computational univalence and higher inductive types which hence gives computational meaning to Homotopy Type Theory and Univalent Foundations. The version of Cubical Type Theory that Agda implements is a variation of the CCHM Cubical Type Theory where the Kan composition operations are decomposed into homogeneous composition and generalized transport. This is what makes the general schema for higher inductive types work, following the CHM paper.
To use the cubical mode Agda needs to be run with the
--cubical
command-line-option or with {-#
OPTIONS --cubical #-}
at the top of the file. There is also a
variant of the cubical mode, activated using
--erased-cubical
, which is described
below.
The cubical mode adds the following features to Agda:
- An interval type and path types
- Generalized transport (
transp
) - Partial elements
- Homogeneous composition (
hcomp
) - Glue types
- Higher inductive types
- Cubical identity types
There is a standard agda/cubical
library for Cubical Agda
available at https://github.com/agda/cubical. This documentation uses
the naming conventions of this library, for a detailed list of all of
the built-in Cubical Agda files and primitives see
Appendix: Cubical Agda primitives. The main design choices of the core part of the
library are explained in
https://homotopytypetheory.org/2018/12/06/cubical-agda/
(lagda rendered version:
https://ice1000.org/2018/12-06-CubicalAgda.html).
The recommended way to get access to the Cubical primitives is to add
the following to the top of a file (this assumes that the
agda/cubical
library is installed and visible to Agda).
{-# OPTIONS --cubical #-}
open import Cubical.Core.Everything
For detailed install instructions for agda/cubical
see:
https://github.com/agda/cubical/blob/master/INSTALL.md. In order to
make this library visible to Agda add
/path/to/cubical/cubical.agda-lib
to .agda/libraries
and
cubical
to .agda/defaults
(where path/to
is the absolute
path to where the agda/cubical
library has been installed). For
details of Agda’s library management see Library Management.
Expert users who do not want to rely on agda/cubical
can just add
the relevant import statements at the top of their file (for details
see Appendix: Cubical Agda primitives). However, for beginners it is
recommended that one uses at least the core part of the
agda/cubical
library.
There is also an older version of the library available at https://github.com/Saizan/cubical-demo/. However this is relying on deprecated features and is not recommended to use.
The interval and path types¶
The key idea of Cubical Type Theory is to add an interval type I :
SSet
(the reason this is in SSet
is because it doesn’t support
the transp
and hcomp
operations). A variable i : I
intuitively corresponds to a point in the real unit interval. In an empty context,
there are only two values of type I
: the two endpoints of the
interval, i0
and i1
.
i0 : I
i1 : I
Elements of the interval form a De Morgan algebra, with minimum
(∧
), maximum (∨
) and negation (~
).
_∧_ : I → I → I
_∨_ : I → I → I
~_ : I → I
All the properties of De Morgan algebras hold definitionally. The
endpoints of the interval i0
and i1
are the bottom and top
elements, respectively.
i0 ∨ i = i
i ∨ i1 = i1
i ∨ j = j ∨ i
i0 ∧ i = i0
i1 ∧ i = i
i ∧ j = j ∧ i
~ (~ i) = i
i0 = ~ i1
~ (i ∨ j) = ~ i ∧ ~ j
~ (i ∧ j) = ~ i ∨ ~ j
The core idea of Homotopy Type Theory and Univalent Foundations is a
correspondence between paths (as in topology) and (proof-relevant)
equalities (as in Martin-Löf’s identity type). This correspondence is
taken very literally in Cubical Agda where a path in a type A
is
represented like a function out of the interval, I → A
. A
path type is in fact a special case of the more general built-in
heterogeneous path types:
-- PathP : ∀ {ℓ} (A : I → Set ℓ) → A i0 → A i1 → Set ℓ
-- Non dependent path types
Path : ∀ {ℓ} (A : Set ℓ) → A → A → Set ℓ
Path A a b = PathP (λ _ → A) a b
The central notion of equality in Cubical Agda is hence heterogeneous
equality (in the sense of PathOver
in HoTT). To define paths we
use λ-abstractions and to apply them we use regular application. For
example, this is the definition of the constant path (or proof of
reflexivity):
refl : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {x : A} → Path A x x
refl {x = x} = λ i → x
Although they use the same syntax, a path is not exactly the same as a function. For example, the following is not valid:
refl : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {x : A} → Path A x x
refl {x = x} = λ (i : I) → x
Because of the intuition that paths correspond to equality PathP (λ
i → A) x y
gets printed as x ≡ y
when A
does not mention
i
. By iterating the path type we can define squares, cubes, and
higher cubes in Agda, making the type theory cubical. For example a
square in A
is built out of 4 points and 4 lines:
Square : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {x0 x1 y0 y1 : A} →
x0 ≡ x1 → y0 ≡ y1 → x0 ≡ y0 → x1 ≡ y1 → Set ℓ
Square p q r s = PathP (λ i → p i ≡ q i) r s
Viewing equalities as functions out of the interval makes it possible to do a lot of equality reasoning in a very direct way:
sym : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {x y : A} → x ≡ y → y ≡ x
sym p = λ i → p (~ i)
cong : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {x y : A} {B : A → Set ℓ} (f : (a : A) → B a) (p : x ≡ y)
→ PathP (λ i → B (p i)) (f x) (f y)
cong f p i = f (p i)
Because of the way functions compute these satisfy some new definitional equalities compared to the standard Agda definitions:
symInv : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {x y : A} (p : x ≡ y) → sym (sym p) ≡ p
symInv p = refl
congId : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {x y : A} (p : x ≡ y) → cong (λ a → a) p ≡ p
congId p = refl
congComp : ∀ {ℓ} {A B C : Set ℓ} (f : A → B) (g : B → C) {x y : A} (p : x ≡ y) →
cong (λ a → g (f a)) p ≡ cong g (cong f p)
congComp f g p = refl
Path types also lets us prove new things are not provable in standard Agda, for example function extensionality (pointwise equal functions are equal) has an extremely simple proof:
funExt : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {B : A → Set ℓ} {f g : (x : A) → B x} →
((x : A) → f x ≡ g x) → f ≡ g
funExt p i x = p x i
Transport¶
While path types are great for reasoning about equality they don’t let us transport along paths between types or even compose paths, which in particular means that we cannot yet prove the induction principle for paths. In order to remedy this we also have a built-in (generalized) transport operation transp and homogeneous composition operations hcomp. The transport operation is generalized in the sense that it lets us specify where it is the identity function.
transp : ∀ {ℓ} (A : I → Set ℓ) (r : I) (a : A i0) → A i1
There is an additional side condition to be satisfied for a usage of transp
to type-check: A
should be a constant function whenever the constraint r = i1
is satisfied. By constant here we mean that A
is definitionally equal to λ _ → A i0
, which in turn requires A i0
and A i1
to be definitionally equal as well.
When r
is i1
, transp A r
will compute as the identity function.
transp A i1 a = a
This is only sound if in such a case A
is a trivial path, as the side condition requires.
It might seems strange that the side condition expects r
and
A
to interact, but both of them can depend on any of the
interval variables in scope, so assuming a specific value for r
can affect what A
looks like.
Some examples of the side condition for different values of r
:
- If
r
is some in-scope variablei
, on whichA
may depend as well, thenA
only needs to be a constant function when substitutingi1
fori
. - If
r
isi0
then there is no restrition onA
, since the side condition is vacuously true. - If
r
isi1
thenA
must be a constant function.
We can use transp
to define regular transport:
transport : ∀ {ℓ} {A B : Set ℓ} → A ≡ B → A → B
transport p a = transp (λ i → p i) i0 a
By combining the transport and min operations we can define the induction principle for paths:
J : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {x : A} (P : ∀ y → x ≡ y → Set ℓ)
(d : P x refl) {y : A} (p : x ≡ y)
→ P y p
J P d p = transport (λ i → P (p i) (λ j → p (i ∧ j))) d
One subtle difference between paths and the propositional equality
type of Agda is that the computation rule for J
does not hold
definitionally. If J
is defined using pattern-matching as in the
Agda standard library then this holds, however as the path types are
not inductively defined this does not hold for the above definition of
J
. In particular, transport in a constant family is only the
identity function up to a path which implies that the computation rule
for J
only holds up to a path:
transportRefl : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} (x : A) → transport refl x ≡ x
transportRefl {A = A} x i = transp (λ _ → A) i x
JRefl : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {x : A} (P : ∀ y → x ≡ y → Set ℓ)
(d : P x refl) → J P d refl ≡ d
JRefl P d = transportRefl d
Internally in Agda the transp
operation computes by cases on the
type, so for example for Σ-types it is computed elementwise. For path
types it is however not yet possible to provide the computation rule
as we need some way to remember the endpoints of the path after
transporting it. Furthermore, this must work for arbitrary higher
dimensional cubes (as we can iterate the path types). For this we
introduce the “homogeneous composition operations” (hcomp
) that
generalize binary composition of paths to n-ary composition of higher
dimensional cubes.
Partial elements¶
In order to describe the homogeneous composition operations we need to
be able to write partially specified n-dimensional cubes (i.e. cubes
where some faces are missing). Given an element of the interval r :
I
there is a predicate IsOne
which represents the constraint r
= i1
. This comes with a proof that i1
is in fact equal to i1
called 1=1 : IsOne i1
. We use Greek letters like φ
or ψ
when such an r
should be thought of as being in the domain of
IsOne
.
Using this we introduce a type of partial elements called Partial φ
A
, this is a special version of IsOne φ → A
with a more
extensional judgmental equality (two elements of Partial φ A
are
considered equal if they represent the same subcube, so the faces of
the cubes can for example be given in different order and the two
elements will still be considered the same). The idea is that
Partial φ A
is the type of cubes in A
that are only defined
when IsOne φ
. There is also a dependent version of this called
PartialP φ A
which allows A
to be defined only when IsOne
φ
.
Partial : ∀ {ℓ} → I → Set ℓ → SSet ℓ
PartialP : ∀ {ℓ} → (φ : I) → Partial φ (Set ℓ) → SSet ℓ
There is a new form of pattern matching that can be used to introduce partial elements:
partialBool : ∀ i → Partial (i ∨ ~ i) Bool
partialBool i (i = i0) = true
partialBool i (i = i1) = false
The term partialBool i
should be thought of a boolean with different
values when (i = i0)
and (i = i1)
. Terms of type Partial φ
A
can also be introduced using a Pattern matching lambda.
partialBool' : ∀ i → Partial (i ∨ ~ i) Bool
partialBool' i = λ { (i = i0) → true
; (i = i1) → false }
When the cases overlap they must agree (note that the order of the cases doesn’t have to match the interval formula exactly):
partialBool'' : ∀ i j → Partial (~ i ∨ i ∨ (i ∧ j)) Bool
partialBool'' i j = λ { (i = i1) → true
; (i = i1) (j = i1) → true
; (i = i0) → false }
Furthermore IsOne i0
is actually absurd.
empty : {A : Set} → Partial i0 A
empty = λ { () }
Cubical Agda also has cubical subtypes as in the CCHM type theory:
_[_↦_] : ∀ {ℓ} (A : Set ℓ) (φ : I) (u : Partial φ A) → SSet ℓ
A [ φ ↦ u ] = Sub A φ u
A term v : A [ φ ↦ u ]
should be thought of as a term of type
A
which is definitionally equal to u : A
when IsOne φ
is
satisfied. Any term u : A
can be seen as an term of A [ φ ↦ u
]
which agrees with itself on φ
:
inS : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {φ : I} (u : A) → A [ φ ↦ (λ _ → u) ]
One can also forget that a partial element agrees with u
on φ
:
outS : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {φ : I} {u : Partial φ A} → A [ φ ↦ u ] → A
They satisfy the following equalities:
outS (inS a) = a
inS {φ = φ} (outS {φ = φ} a) = a
outS {φ = i1} {u} _ = u 1=1
Note that given a : A [ φ ↦ u ]
and α : IsOne φ
, it is not the case
that outS a = u α
; however, underneath the pattern binding (φ = i1)
,
one has outS a = u 1=1
.
With all of this cubical infrastructure we can now describe the
hcomp
operations.
Homogeneous composition¶
The homogeneous composition operations generalize binary composition of paths so that we can compose multiple composable cubes.
hcomp : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {φ : I} (u : I → Partial φ A) (u0 : A) → A
When calling hcomp {φ = φ} u u0
Agda makes sure that u0
agrees
with u i0
on φ
. The idea is that u0
is the base and u
specifies the sides of an open box. This is hence an open (higher
dimensional) cube where the side opposite of u0
is missing. The
hcomp
operation then gives us the missing side opposite of
u0
. For example binary composition of paths can be written as:
compPath : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {x y z : A} → x ≡ y → y ≡ z → x ≡ z
compPath {x = x} p q i = hcomp (λ j → λ { (i = i0) → x
; (i = i1) → q j })
(p i)
Pictorially we are given p : x ≡ y
and q : y ≡ z
, and the
composite of the two paths is obtained by computing the missing lid of
this open square:
x z
^ ^
| |
x | | q j
| |
x ----------> y
p i
In the drawing the direction i
goes left-to-right and j
goes
bottom-to-top. As we are constructing a path from x
to z
along
i
we have i : I
in the context already and we put p i
as
bottom. The direction j
that we are doing the composition in is
abstracted in the first argument to hcomp
.
Note that the partial element u
does not have to specify
all the sides of the open box, giving more sides simply gives you
more control on the result of hcomp
.
For example if we omit the (i = i0) → x
side in the
definition of compPath
we still get a valid term of type
A
. However, that term would reduce to hcomp (\ j → \ { () }) x
when i = i0
and so that definition would not build
a path that starts from x
.
We can also define homogeneous filling of cubes as
hfill : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {φ : I}
(u : ∀ i → Partial φ A) (u0 : A [ φ ↦ u i0 ])
(i : I) → A
hfill {φ = φ} u u0 i = hcomp (λ j → λ { (φ = i1) → u (i ∧ j) 1=1
; (i = i0) → outS u0 })
(outS u0)
When i
is i0
this is u0
and when i
is i1
this is
hcomp u u0
. This can hence be seen as giving us the interior of an
open box. In the special case of the square above hfill
gives us a
direct cubical proof that composing p
with refl
is p
.
compPathRefl : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {x y : A} (p : x ≡ y) → compPath p refl ≡ p
compPathRefl {x = x} {y = y} p j i = hfill (λ _ → λ { (i = i0) → x
; (i = i1) → y })
(inS (p i))
(~ j)
Glue types¶
In order to be able to prove the univalence theorem we also have to
add “Glue” types. These lets us turn equivalences between types into
paths between types. An equivalence of types A
and B
is
defined as a map f : A → B
such that its fibers are contractible.
fiber : ∀ {ℓ} {A B : Set ℓ} (f : A → B) (y : B) → Set ℓ
fiber {A = A} f y = Σ[ x ∈ A ] f x ≡ y
isContr : ∀ {ℓ} → Set ℓ → Set ℓ
isContr A = Σ[ x ∈ A ] (∀ y → x ≡ y)
record isEquiv {ℓ} {A B : Set ℓ} (f : A → B) : Set ℓ where
field
equiv-proof : (y : B) → isContr (fiber f y)
_≃_ : ∀ {ℓ} (A B : Set ℓ) → Set ℓ
A ≃ B = Σ[ f ∈ (A → B) ] (isEquiv f)
The simplest example of an equivalence is the identity function.
idfun : ∀ {ℓ} → (A : Set ℓ) → A → A
idfun _ x = x
idIsEquiv : ∀ {ℓ} (A : Set ℓ) → isEquiv (idfun A)
equiv-proof (idIsEquiv A) y =
((y , refl) , λ z i → z .snd (~ i) , λ j → z .snd (~ i ∨ j))
idEquiv : ∀ {ℓ} (A : Set ℓ) → A ≃ A
idEquiv A = (idfun A , idIsEquiv A)
An important special case of equivalent types are isomorphic types (i.e. types with maps going back and forth which are mutually inverse): https://github.com/agda/cubical/blob/master/Cubical/Foundations/Isomorphism.agda.
As everything has to work up to higher dimensions the Glue types take
a partial family of types that are equivalent to the base type A
:
Glue : ∀ {ℓ ℓ'} (A : Set ℓ) {φ : I}
→ Partial φ (Σ[ T ∈ Set ℓ' ] T ≃ A) → Set ℓ'
These come with a constructor and eliminator:
glue : ∀ {ℓ ℓ'} {A : Set ℓ} {φ : I} {Te : Partial φ (Σ[ T ∈ Set ℓ' ] T ≃ A)}
→ PartialP φ T → A → Glue A Te
unglue : ∀ {ℓ ℓ'} {A : Set ℓ} (φ : I) {Te : Partial φ (Σ[ T ∈ Set ℓ' ] T ≃ A)}
→ Glue A Te → A
Using Glue types we can turn an equivalence of types into a path as follows:
ua : ∀ {ℓ} {A B : Set ℓ} → A ≃ B → A ≡ B
ua {_} {A} {B} e i = Glue B (λ { (i = i0) → (A , e)
; (i = i1) → (B , idEquiv B) })
The idea is that we glue A
together with B
when i = i0
using e
and B
with itself when i = i1
using the identity
equivalence. This hence gives us the key part of univalence: a
function for turning equivalences into paths. The other part of
univalence is that this map itself is an equivalence which follows
from the computation rule for ua
:
uaβ : ∀ {ℓ} {A B : Set ℓ} (e : A ≃ B) (x : A) → transport (ua e) x ≡ e .fst x
uaβ e x = transportRefl (e .fst x)
Transporting along the path that we get from applying ua
to an
equivalence is hence the same as applying the equivalence. This is
what makes it possible to use the univalence axiom computationally in
Cubical Agda: we can package up our equivalences as paths, do equality
reasoning using these paths, and in the end transport along the paths
in order to compute with the equivalences.
We have the following equalities:
Glue A {i1} Te = Te 1=1 .fst
unglue φ (glue t a) = a
glue (\ { (φ = i1) -> g}) (unglue φ g) = g
unglue i1 {Te} g = Te 1=1 .snd .fst g
glue {φ = i1} t a = t 1=1
For more results about Glue types and univalence see https://github.com/agda/cubical/blob/master/Cubical/Core/Glue.agda and https://github.com/agda/cubical/blob/master/Cubical/Foundations/Univalence.agda. For some examples of what can be done with this for working with binary and unary numbers see https://github.com/agda/cubical/blob/master/Cubical/Data/BinNat/BinNat.agda.
Higher inductive types¶
Cubical Agda also lets us directly define higher inductive types as datatypes with path constructors. For example the circle and torus can be defined as:
data S¹ : Set where
base : S¹
loop : base ≡ base
data Torus : Set where
point : Torus
line1 : point ≡ point
line2 : point ≡ point
square : PathP (λ i → line1 i ≡ line1 i) line2 line2
Functions out of higher inductive types can then be defined using pattern-matching:
t2c : Torus → S¹ × S¹
t2c point = (base , base)
t2c (line1 i) = (loop i , base)
t2c (line2 j) = (base , loop j)
t2c (square i j) = (loop i , loop j)
c2t : S¹ × S¹ → Torus
c2t (base , base) = point
c2t (loop i , base) = line1 i
c2t (base , loop j) = line2 j
c2t (loop i , loop j) = square i j
When giving the cases for the path and square constructors we have to
make sure that the function maps the boundary to the right thing. For
instance the following definition does not pass Agda’s typechecker as
the boundary of the last case does not match up with the expected
boundary of the square constructor (as the line1
and line2
cases are mixed up).
c2t_bad : S¹ × S¹ → Torus
c2t_bad (base , base) = point
c2t_bad (loop i , base) = line2 i
c2t_bad (base , loop j) = line1 j
c2t_bad (loop i , loop j) = square i j
Functions defined by pattern-matching on higher inductive types compute definitionally, for all constructors.
c2t-t2c : ∀ (t : Torus) → c2t (t2c t) ≡ t
c2t-t2c point = refl
c2t-t2c (line1 _) = refl
c2t-t2c (line2 _) = refl
c2t-t2c (square _ _) = refl
t2c-c2t : ∀ (p : S¹ × S¹) → t2c (c2t p) ≡ p
t2c-c2t (base , base) = refl
t2c-c2t (base , loop _) = refl
t2c-c2t (loop _ , base) = refl
t2c-c2t (loop _ , loop _) = refl
By turning this isomorphism into an equivalence we get a direct proof that the torus is equal to two circles.
Torus≡S¹×S¹ : Torus ≡ S¹ × S¹
Torus≡S¹×S¹ = isoToPath (iso t2c c2t t2c-c2t c2t-t2c)
Cubical Agda also supports parameterized and recursive higher inductive types, for example propositional truncation (squash types) is defined as:
data ∥_∥ {ℓ} (A : Set ℓ) : Set ℓ where
∣_∣ : A → ∥ A ∥
squash : ∀ (x y : ∥ A ∥) → x ≡ y
isProp : ∀ {ℓ} → Set ℓ → Set ℓ
isProp A = (x y : A) → x ≡ y
recPropTrunc : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {P : Set ℓ} → isProp P → (A → P) → ∥ A ∥ → P
recPropTrunc Pprop f ∣ x ∣ = f x
recPropTrunc Pprop f (squash x y i) =
Pprop (recPropTrunc Pprop f x) (recPropTrunc Pprop f y) i
For many more examples of higher inductive types see: https://github.com/agda/cubical/tree/master/Cubical/HITs.
Cubical identity types and computational HoTT/UF¶
As mentioned above the computation rule for J
does not hold
definitionally for path types. Cubical Agda solves this by introducing
a cubical identity type. The
https://github.com/agda/cubical/blob/master/Cubical/Core/Id.agda file
exports all of the primitives for this type, including the notation
_≡_
and a J
eliminator that computes definitionally on
refl
.
The cubical identity type and the path type are equivalent, so all of the results for one can be transported to the other one (using univalence). Using this we have implemented an interface to HoTT/UF which provides the user with the key primitives of Homotopy Type Theory and Univalent Foundations implemented using cubical primitives under the hood. This hence gives an axiom free version of HoTT/UF which computes properly.
module Cubical.Core.HoTT-UF where
open import Cubical.Core.Id public
using ( _≡_ -- The identity type.
; refl -- Unfortunately, pattern matching on refl is not available.
; J -- Until it is, you have to use the induction principle J.
; transport -- As in the HoTT Book.
; ap
; _∙_
; _⁻¹
; _≡⟨_⟩_ -- Standard equational reasoning.
; _∎
; funExt -- Function extensionality
-- (can also be derived from univalence).
; Σ -- Sum type. Needed to define contractible types, equivalences
; _,_ -- and univalence.
; pr₁ -- The eta rule is available.
; pr₂
; isProp -- The usual notions of proposition, contractible type, set.
; isContr
; isSet
; isEquiv -- A map with contractible fibers
-- (Voevodsky's version of the notion).
; _≃_ -- The type of equivalences between two given types.
; EquivContr -- A formulation of univalence.
; ∥_∥ -- Propositional truncation.
; ∣_∣ -- Map into the propositional truncation.
; ∥∥-isProp -- A truncated type is a proposition.
; ∥∥-recursion -- Non-dependent elimination.
; ∥∥-induction -- Dependent elimination.
)
In order to get access to only the HoTT/UF primitives start a file as follows:
{-# OPTIONS --cubical #-}
open import Cubical.Core.HoTT-UF
However, even though this interface exists it is still recommended
that one uses the cubical identity types unless one really need J
to compute on refl
. The reason for this is that the syntax for
path types does not work for the identity types, making many proofs
more involved as the only way to reason about them is using J
.
Furthermore, the path types satisfy many useful definitional
equalities that the identity types don’t.
Cubical Agda with erased glue¶
The option --erased-cubical
enables a variant of Cubical
Agda in which glue (and the other builtins defined in
Agda.Builtin.Cubical.Glue
) must only be used in
erased settings.
Regular Cubical Agda code can import code that uses
--erased-cubical
. Regular Cubical Agda code can also be
imported from code that uses --erased-cubical
, but names
defined using Cubical Agda are treated as if they had been marked as
erased, with some exceptions related to pattern matching:
- Matching on a non-erased imported constructor does not, on its own, make Agda treat the right-hand side as erased.
- Non-erased imported constructors count as non-erased for the purposes of the run-time mode rule that one “cannot pattern match on erased arguments, unless there is at most one valid case (not counting erased constructors)”.
The reason for these exceptions is that it should be possible to
import the code from modules that use --cubical
, in which
the non-erased constructors are not treated as erased.
Note that names that are re-exported from a Cubical Agda module using
open import M args public
are seen as defined using Cubical Agda.
References¶
Cyril Cohen, Thierry Coquand, Simon Huber and Anders Mörtberg; “Cubical Type Theory: a constructive interpretation of the univalence axiom”.
Thierry Coquand, Simon Huber, Anders Mörtberg; “On Higher Inductive Types in Cubical Type Theory”.
Appendix: Cubical Agda primitives¶
The Cubical Agda primitives and internals are exported by a series of
files found in the lib/prim/Agda/Builtin/Cubical
directory of
Agda. The agda/cubical
library exports all of these primitives
with the names used throughout this document. Experts might find it
useful to know what is actually exported as there are quite a few
primitives available that are not really exported by agda/cubical
,
so the goal of this section is to list the contents of these
files. However, for regular users and beginners the agda/cubical
library should be sufficient and this section can safely be ignored.
The key file with primitives is Agda.Primitive.Cubical
. It exports
the following BUILTIN
, primitives and postulates:
{-# BUILTIN INTERVAL I #-} -- I : SSet
{-# BUILTIN IZERO i0 #-}
{-# BUILTIN IONE i1 #-}
infix 30 primINeg
infixr 20 primIMin primIMax
primitive
primIMin : I → I → I -- _∧_
primIMax : I → I → I -- _∨_
primINeg : I → I -- ~_
{-# BUILTIN ISONE IsOne #-} -- IsOne : I → SSet
postulate
itIsOne : IsOne i1 -- 1=1
IsOne1 : ∀ i j → IsOne i → IsOne (primIMax i j)
IsOne2 : ∀ i j → IsOne j → IsOne (primIMax i j)
{-# BUILTIN ITISONE itIsOne #-}
{-# BUILTIN ISONE1 IsOne1 #-}
{-# BUILTIN ISONE2 IsOne2 #-}
{-# BUILTIN PARTIAL Partial #-}
{-# BUILTIN PARTIALP PartialP #-}
postulate
isOneEmpty : ∀ {a} {A : Partial i0 (Set a)} → PartialP i0 A
{-# BUILTIN ISONEEMPTY isOneEmpty #-}
primitive
primPOr : ∀ {a} (i j : I) {A : Partial (primIMax i j) (Set a)}
→ PartialP i (λ z → A (IsOne1 i j z)) → PartialP j (λ z → A (IsOne2 i j z))
→ PartialP (primIMax i j) A
-- Computes in terms of primHComp and primTransp
primComp : ∀ {a} (A : (i : I) → Set (a i)) {φ : I} → (∀ i → Partial φ (A i)) → (a : A i0) → A i1
syntax primPOr p q u t = [ p ↦ u , q ↦ t ]
primitive
primTransp : ∀ {a} (A : (i : I) → Set (a i)) (φ : I) → (a : A i0) → A i1
primHComp : ∀ {a} {A : Set a} {φ : I} → (∀ i → Partial φ A) → A → A
The Path types are exported by Agda.Builtin.Cubical.Path
:
postulate
PathP : ∀ {ℓ} (A : I → Set ℓ) → A i0 → A i1 → Set ℓ
{-# BUILTIN PATHP PathP #-}
infix 4 _≡_
_≡_ : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} → A → A → Set ℓ
_≡_ {A = A} = PathP (λ _ → A)
{-# BUILTIN PATH _≡_ #-}
The Cubical subtypes are exported by Agda.Builtin.Cubical.Sub
:
{-# BUILTIN SUB Sub #-}
postulate
inc : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {φ} (x : A) → Sub A φ (λ _ → x)
{-# BUILTIN SUBIN inS #-}
primitive
primSubOut : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {φ : I} {u : Partial φ A} → Sub _ φ u → A
The Glue types are exported by Agda.Builtin.Cubical.Glue
:
record isEquiv {ℓ ℓ'} {A : Set ℓ} {B : Set ℓ'} (f : A → B) : Set (ℓ ⊔ ℓ') where
field
equiv-proof : (y : B) → isContr (fiber f y)
infix 4 _≃_
_≃_ : ∀ {ℓ ℓ'} (A : Set ℓ) (B : Set ℓ') → Set (ℓ ⊔ ℓ')
A ≃ B = Σ (A → B) \ f → (isEquiv f)
equivFun : ∀ {ℓ ℓ'} {A : Set ℓ} {B : Set ℓ'} → A ≃ B → A → B
equivFun e = fst e
equivProof : ∀ {la lt} (T : Set la) (A : Set lt) → (w : T ≃ A) → (a : A)
→ ∀ ψ → (Partial ψ (fiber (w .fst) a)) → fiber (w .fst) a
equivProof A B w a ψ fb = contr' {A = fiber (w .fst) a} (w .snd .equiv-proof a) ψ fb
where
contr' : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} → isContr A → (φ : I) → (u : Partial φ A) → A
contr' {A = A} (c , p) φ u = hcomp (λ i → λ { (φ = i1) → p (u 1=1) i
; (φ = i0) → c }) c
{-# BUILTIN EQUIV _≃_ #-}
{-# BUILTIN EQUIVFUN equivFun #-}
{-# BUILTIN EQUIVPROOF equivProof #-}
primitive
primGlue : ∀ {ℓ ℓ'} (A : Set ℓ) {φ : I}
→ (T : Partial φ (Set ℓ')) → (e : PartialP φ (λ o → T o ≃ A))
→ Set ℓ'
prim^glue : ∀ {ℓ ℓ'} {A : Set ℓ} {φ : I}
→ {T : Partial φ (Set ℓ')} → {e : PartialP φ (λ o → T o ≃ A)}
→ PartialP φ T → A → primGlue A T e
prim^unglue : ∀ {ℓ ℓ'} {A : Set ℓ} {φ : I}
→ {T : Partial φ (Set ℓ')} → {e : PartialP φ (λ o → T o ≃ A)}
→ primGlue A T e → A
primFaceForall : (I → I) → I
-- pathToEquiv proves that transport is an equivalence (for details
-- see Agda.Builtin.Cubical.Glue). This is needed internally.
{-# BUILTIN PATHTOEQUIV pathToEquiv #-}
Note that the Glue types are uncurried in agda/cubical
to make
them more pleasant to use:
Glue : ∀ {ℓ ℓ'} (A : Set ℓ) {φ : I}
→ (Te : Partial φ (Σ[ T ∈ Set ℓ' ] T ≃ A))
→ Set ℓ'
Glue A Te = primGlue A (λ x → Te x .fst) (λ x → Te x .snd)
The Agda.Builtin.Cubical.Id
exports the cubical identity types:
postulate
Id : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} → A → A → Set ℓ
{-# BUILTIN ID Id #-}
{-# BUILTIN CONID conid #-}
primitive
primDepIMin : _
primIdFace : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {x y : A} → Id x y → I
primIdPath : ∀ {ℓ} {A : Set ℓ} {x y : A} → Id x y → x ≡ y
primitive
primIdJ : ∀ {ℓ ℓ'} {A : Set ℓ} {x : A} (P : ∀ y → Id x y → Set ℓ') →
P x (conid i1 (λ i → x)) → ∀ {y} (p : Id x y) → P y p
primitive
primIdElim : ∀ {a c} {A : Set a} {x : A}
(C : (y : A) → Id x y → Set c) →
((φ : I) (y : A [ φ ↦ (λ _ → x) ])
(w : (x ≡ outS y) [ φ ↦ (λ { (φ = i1) → \ _ → x}) ]) →
C (outS y) (conid φ (outS w))) →
{y : A} (p : Id x y) → C y p